May 28, 2024

Knowns and unknowns

A comment on Neef and Chang (2024)

This is a comment to the paper by Nicole Neef and Soo-Eun Chang “Knowns and unknowns about the neurobiology of stuttering” (PLoS Biology. 2024). In a slightly different form, it was originally intended as a comment in PLoS Biology, but because of spam problems, the comment function is currently switched off there. Therefore, I now publish it here.

As I wrote in the previous post (see below), the data about stuttering is like pieces of a large puzzle, and we must try to put the pieces together. To this, the paper by Neef and Chang is a valuable contribution; however, I would like to make some remarks.

Is stuttering a breakdown of control?

A person who is stuttering may experience this as a loss of control, but this subjective impression does not imply that the control of speech has actually broken down in the brain. Instead, the inhibition of speech against the person’s will may be a regular response of the speech control to an error signal elicited by a mismatch between sensory prediction and sensory feedback. This could be evoked by incorrect predictions (e.g., Max et al., 2004; Tian & Poeppel, 2012) or, as I assume, by impaired feedback processing.

Whether stuttering is a breakdown of speech control is unknown, and ignoring this can lead down the wrong path: to the search for a speech network deficit responsible for the supposed breakdown, whereas the real problem may be an insufficient or wrong interaction with other neural networks, e.g., attention, sensory system, or the default mode network. The fact that most stutterers are spontaneously fluent in certain conditions (e.g., choral speeh, altered auditory feedback) suggests that their speech network is basically functional.

Attention regulation and auditory processing

Two things that, from my perspective, are important elements of our knowledge about stuttering, remain unmentioned in the article. From many studies, we know that stutterers, as a group, have deficits in attention regulation and auditory processing. This knowledge has indeed been gained primarily through behavioral studies, but there are also neurological findings.

As for the auditory system, Salmelin et al. (1998), using MEG, found that adults who stutter and controls differed in the functional organization of the auditory cortices. Using EEG, impaired non-linguistic auditory processing was found in pre-school children (Kaganovich, Hampton Wray, & Weber-Fox, 2010) and adults who stutter (Kikuchi et al., 2011, 2017; Saltuklaroglu et al., 2017). As for the attention system, Chang et al. (2018) found that stuttering children exhibited anomalous functional connectivities within and between neural networks that are involved in attention regulation.

Considering both attention regulation and auditory processing (particularly the processing of the auditory feedback of speech) as possible causal factors in stuttering may help understand some mysterious features of stuttering, among them the sex ratio: attention deficit/ hyperactivity disorder is about three times more frequent, and auditory processing disorder is about two times more frequent in males than in females (Ramtekkar et al., 2010; Chermak & Musiek, 1997).

Singing

For the fluency-inducing effect of singing, it is not required that the melody follows a fixed pattern in terms of pitch, rhythm, or volume dynamics. In a behavioral study (Glover et al., 1996), stutterers read and sung prose passages at a normal and a fast rate. In the two singing conditions, the participants had to spontaneously create idiosyncratic melodies, and their singing was not always very “musical”, but stuttering was reduced by 75% on average in singing as compared with reading, and there was no difference in stuttering frequency with rate.

This suggests that the fluency during song is not due to auditory memory retrieval or less freedom in terms of pitch, rhythm, or voice intensity. The fluency may rather result from increased reliance on auditory feedback and improved auditory-motor integration, since singing requires the integration of auditory feedback mechanisms with the vocal motor system (Zarate & Zatorre, 2008).

Dorsal laryngeal motor cortex

The Neef and Chang point to an interesting relationship: dorsal laryngeal motor cortex (dLMC) (1) is involved in auditory feedback control during singing and (2) in sentence reading under delayed auditory feedback, (3) supported the effect of a fluency-shaping therapy, and (4) children who recovered from stuttering exhibited an increased gray matter growth rate in the dorsal premotor cortex, a region near to the dLMC, which is involved in the processing of auditory feedback.

Although the mentioned fluency-shaping program (Kassel stuttering therapy) does not intend to improve auditory-motor integration (for learning the speech technique, they use computer-generated visual feedback of voice intensity), the application of the technique in everyday situations might require more attentive monitoring via auditory feedback than habitual speech did. Therefore, the question arises: Is it not likely that, in all four cases, speech fluency improved with increased integration of auditory feedback in speech control?

 

to the top


 

January 12, 2024

Let’s put the puzzle together!

Do we need a theory of stuttering?

Some years ago, I had a talk with a well-known expert in the field of stuttering research. I hoped he would be interested in my theoretical ideas about the causes of stuttering, but he told me that he was not interested in theories at all. I was surprised and didn’t know what to reply.

I had believed he was searching for the causes of stuttering (and I still think he is searching for those causes), but apparently he was not aware of the fact that causes are always theoretical. Causation is a purely theoretical concept; there is no empirical evidence for causation to exist at all. This doesn’t mean that causation is not real. It only means that empirical research can never find causes.

We are deeply convinced that causality exists. We are convinced that there are relationships between causes and effects. When I throw a stone against a windowpane and the pane gets broken, then I’m convinced that my action caused the pane to get broken. From the subjective experience that our actions have effects, our belief in causation came about. Asking about causes has become the essential way we understand things and events in the world.

Causality is not empirical

Why can empirical research not provide evidence of causation? In the above example, an objective observer can only find a temporal correlation between two events: the pane goes to pieces each time a sufficiently big stone is thrown against it with sufficient power. The conclusion that throwing the stone causes the pane to break is a very plausible but nevertheless purely theoretical conclusion, since the causation itself is not observable.

When we observe a repeated temporal succession of two events A and B or find a statistical correlation between two variables A and B, we can, strictly speaking, never know if there is a causal connection between them. The reason is: there may be an unknown cause C that caused both A and B and the correlation between them, without there being any causality between A and B.

An unknown underlying cause C is extremely implausible in the above example of the broken windowpane. But it cannot be excluded if, for example, a positive correlation is found between the amount of a brain structure anomaly and stuttering severity. There is not only the chicken-or-egg question: is the structural anomaly a cause or consequence of stuttering? From the data alone, we can’t even infer whether there is a causal connection at all between the two variables.

It is therefore impossible to logically derive a causal theory from empirical data alone. Theories are rather the product of speculative thinking about how things may work. A theory arises from an idea, and sometimes perhaps from daydreaming (chemist August Kekulé reported he first saw the annular shape of the benzene molecule in a dream). But the way a theory has come into being is irrelevant to the question whether it is correct or not.

The value of empirical data

To be valid, that is, possibly correct, a theory has to be consistent with all relevant empirical data. From that, it follows: the more data is provided, the greater the likelihood that a theory is inconsistent with all of them, and that is, the more data we have, the smaller the number of valid theories. At best, only one valid theory remains; then we have good reasons to consider it correct. In the case of a newly discovered phenomenon about which little data is available, further studies may be needed to test the theory, that is, to compare predictions derived from the theory with the data obtained from these studies. However, agreement with a prediction doesn’t mean more than that the theory is consistent with those data. In this regard, there is no difference between data obtained in the past and in the future: a valid theory has to be consistent with all.

Developmental stuttering is not a newly discovered phenomenon; we have a ton of data about it. Of course, the author of a theory cannot check his theory against all these data, but it should be easy for critics to support their objections with data and, in this way, to falsify an incorrect theory. So, the value of data is not that you can derive theories from it, but that you can use it to find out and show which theories are wrong. In this way, empirical data serves for the development of theories and for progress in science.

Consistency with all relevant data is not the only criterion for evaluating theories. A critic can also show that the theory is incoherent or inconsistent in itself (if that is the case) or that the theory does not provide the answers we expect from a good theory. Here is a list of questions a proper theory of stuttering should answer.

Let’s put the puzzle together!

Given the vast amount of data about stuttering that are available today, from behavioral research and from brain research, it is probably not for lack of data that we still don’t understand the causes of the disorder. I rather think we have a lack theoretical research and discussion. Empirical data is like pieces of a puzzle, and what we have to do is put the puzzle together. This has been my endeavor for more then 10 years.

to the top

previous page